unjust world theory


After all, the world as a whole has come a long way since the days when war was pretty much seen as a sport and a rite of manhood. Many vomited blood. [2] Hypothesized dimensions of just-world beliefs include belief in an unjust world,[33] beliefs in immanent justice and ultimate justice,[34] hope for justice, and belief in one's ability to reduce injustice. Readily it can be accepted that soldiers killing other soldiers is part of the nature of warfare for which soldiers ought to be prepared and trained, but when soldiers turn their weapons against non-combatants, or pursue their enemy beyond what is reasonable, then they are no longer committing legitimate acts of war but acts of murder. The extreme intrinsicism of Kant can be criticized on various grounds, the most pertinent here being the value of self-interest itself.

So why does the just-world phenomenon happen?
War should always be a last resort. The Japanese population did not have the same economic incentive to fully support their own government. On this topic, Lifton and Mitchell affirm: “…we have (…) insisted upon the ethical justification of our use of revolutionary new weapons that killed hundreds of thousands of people, and in that way created a counterfeit universe in which weaponry many times more destructive than those early bombs is also honored and legitimized as serving moral purposes.”[7].

[39][40][41], Studies of demographic differences, including gender and racial differences, have not shown systemic differences, but do suggest racial differences, with blacks and African Americans having the lowest levels of belief in a just world. It was composed by two conventions, that each instituted a set of treaties signed by all major nations, such as the “Declaration Prohibiting the Discharge of Projectiles and Explosives from Balloons”, signed in 1907.[29]. The possession of right intention is ostensibly less problematic. For a nation threatened by invasion, other forms of retaliation or defense may be available, such as civil disobedience, or even forming alliances with other small nations to equalize the odds. Even before dropping the atomic bombs, the United States had dropped numerous traditional bombs over entire cities. Lerner summarized his findings and his theoretical work in his 1980 monograph The Belief in a Just World: A Fundamental Delusion. 3 (June 2012): 515–545 (accessed November 2, 2017), 521. However, intrinsicists (who claim that there are certain acts that are good or bad in themselves) may also decree that no morality can exist in the state of war: they may claim that it can only exist in a peaceful situation in which, for instance, recourse exists to conflict resolving institutions.

[13], But there was one diplomatic effort the American diplomacy refused to make: to soften the unconditional surrender demand. Archive for the Psychology of Religion / Archiv für Religionspychologie. If she should persist in her fight to the end, she had still a great military force.”[21]. The aftermath of war involves the relinquishing of armed conflict as a means of resolving disputes and the donning of more civil modes of conduct but it also raises questions concerning the nature of the post bellum justice. In such examples (e.g, Rwanda, 1994), a people’s justification of destructiveness and killing to whatever relative degree they hold to be justifiable triumphs over attempts to establish the laws of peaceful interaction into this separate bloody realm; and in some wars, people fighting for their land or nation prefer to pick up the cudgel rather than the rapier, as Leo Tolstoy notes in War and Peace (Book 4.Ch.2), to sidestep the etiquette or war in favor securing their land from occupational or invading forces. It is also feared that the policy of preemption slips easily into the machinations of “false flag operations” in which a pretext for war is created by a contrived theatrical or actual stunt – of dressing one’s own soldiers up in the enemy’s uniforms, for instance, and having them attack a military or even civilian target so as to gain political backing for a war.
Multiple attempts to reach agreements were made with not much success. [10] Eric Patterson, “Just War Theory & Terrorism,” Providence 4 (Summer 2016): 39. The CIA manual on assassination (1954, cf. Yet the just war theorist wishes to underline the need to attempt all other solutions but also to tie the justice of the war to the other principles of jus ad bellum too. The most commonly understood version of just war theory is grounded in these biblical ideals, simplified into five major points. [29] Library of Congress. The next principle is that of reasonable success. Against these two ethical positions, just war theory offers a series of principles that aim to retain a plausible moral framework for war. When making attributions, focus on looking at all elements of the situation. American Psychological Association. [35] Other work has focused on looking at the different domains in which the belief may function; individuals may have different just-world beliefs for the personal domain, the sociopolitical domain, the social domain, etc. On the whole the principles offered by jus ad bellum are useful guidelines for reviewing the morality of going to war that are not tied to the intrinsicist’s absolutism or consequentialist’s open-endedness. Should a war be indecisive though, the character of the peace would presumably be formed by the character of the ceasefire – namely, the cessation of fighting would imply a mere hiatus in which the belligerents regain the time and resources to stock their defenses and prepare for further fighting. Papers should be suitable for approx. It has often been remarked that justice, like history, is written by the victors. The elements that are taken into consideration during this section are: legitimate authority (the war decision must be made by a political authority), just cause (the decision is a matter of self-defense and protection of citizen’s lives), right intent (it should ultimately seek order and not revenge), likelihood of success (it is inappropriate to engage in military efforts if a victory is probable), proportionality of ends (engaging in military effort should be a proportional response), and last resort (all diplomatic efforts have been exhausted). Through Japan’s eyes, the unconditional surrender request meant that it had to give up its national identity. On grounds of proportionality, the policy would also be acceptable, for if one man or woman (a legitimate target by virtue of his or her aggression) should die to avoid further bloodshed or to secure a quicker victory, then surely assassination is covered by the just war theory? It has often been recognized that war unleashes forces and powers that soon get beyond the grips of the leaders and generals to control – there is too much “fog” in war, as Clausewitz noted, but that fog is also a moral haze in which truth and trust are early casualties.

It also sent the message that having control over atomic power could guarantee the control of a nation over another. The principle of responsibility re-asserts the burden of abiding by rules in times of peace on those acting in war to remind them that one day they will once more take up civilian status and should be prepared to do so conscientiously, free of any guilt from war crimes. Even though it is limited in some aspects, the Just War Theory traces a clear ethical guideline that addresses the before, during, and after a war. Others, avoiding a rights analysis for it produces many problems on delineating the boundaries of rights and the bearers, may argue that those who join the army (or who have even been pressed into conscription) come to terms with being a target, and hence their own deaths. The just world phenomenon might explain why people sometimes fail to help or feel compassion for the homeless, for addicts, or for victims of violence. [45][clarification needed], Belief in unjust world has been linked to increased self-handicapping, criminality, defensive coping, anger and perceived future risk.